-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 5
/
BufferStockTheory-NoAppendix.tex
executable file
·1425 lines (1151 loc) · 136 KB
/
BufferStockTheory-NoAppendix.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
\documentclass[BufferStockTheory]{subfiles}
% WARNING: AuCTeX local variables only get reset when file is loaded
% and differ between this file and BufferStockTheory.tex
% so must re-load whichever file you want to compile with C-x C-v
% WARNING: Different AucTeX execution depending on whether
% 0. Being compiled as standalone document
% * Compile main once
% * Then compile this one
% * Keep compiling until nothing changes
% 0. Being compiled as subfile of main document
% * Just compile main document repeatedly
\input{./econtexRoot}
\input{\LaTeXInputs/econtex_onlyinsubfile}
\onlyinsubfile{\externaldocument{BufferStockTheory}} % Get xrefs -- esp to appendix -- from main file; only works properly if main file has already been compiled;
\begin{document}
% Attempted to make all lines used for Web version contain {Web} (or version with only single curly brace at end) so can be removed with sed
\providecommand{\versn}{pdf} % Version; like, web or pdf or journal submission
\ifthenelse{\boolean{Web}}{ % {Web}
\renewcommand{\versn}{Web} % Too hard to figure out passing -output-directory through make4ht through htlatex, so web version is compiled with junk files in main directory
\renewcommand{\rootFromOut}{.} % {Web}
}{} % {Web}
% Tiny info header at top to track git commit
%\hfill{\tiny \jobname~\versn~\today~{at} \DTMcurrenttime, \input{\ResourcesDir/.git-source-commit}~~\input{\ResourcesDir/.git-public-commit}}
\title{Theoretical Foundations of \\ Buffer Stock Saving}
\author{Christopher D. Carroll\authNum}
\keywords{Precautionary saving, buffer stock saving, marginal propensity to consume, permanent income hypothesis, income fluctuation problem}
\jelclass{D81, D91, E21 \par
\href{https://econ-ark.org}{\includegraphics{\ResourcesDir/PoweredByEconARK}}
}
\renewcommand{\forcedate}{October 11, 2021}\date{\forcedate}
\maketitle
\hypertarget{abstract}{}
\begin{abstract}
This paper builds foundations for rigorous and intuitive understanding of `buffer stock' saving models (\cite{bewleyPIH}-like models with a wealth target), pairing each theoretical result with quantitative illustrations. After describing conditions under which a consumption function exists, the paper articulates stricter `Growth Impatience' conditions that guarantee alternative forms of stability --- either at the population level, or for individual consumers. Together, the numerical tools and analytical results constitute a comprehensive toolkit for understanding buffer stock models.
\end{abstract}
% Various resources
\hypertarget{links}{}
\begin{footnotesize}
\parbox{0.9\textwidth}{
\begin{center}
\begin{tabbing}
\texttt{Dashboard:~} \= \= \texttt{\url{https://econ-ark.org/materials/BufferStockTheory?dashboard}} \\
\texttt{~~~REMARK:~} \> \> \texttt{\url{https://econ-ark.org/materials/BufferStockTheory}} \\ % Owner is defined in Resources/owner.tex
\texttt{~~~~~html:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/}{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/}} \\ % Owner is defined in Resources/owner.tex
\texttt{~~~~~~PDF:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/BufferStockTheory.pdf}{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/BufferStockTheory.pdf}} \\ % Owner is defined in Resources/owner.tex
\texttt{~~~Slides:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/BufferStockTheory-Slides.pdf}{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/BufferStockTheory-Slides.pdf}} \\
\texttt{~Appendix:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory\#Appendices}{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory\#Appendices}} \\
\texttt{~~~GitHub:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://github.com/\owner/BufferStockTheory}{https://github.com/\owner/BufferStockTheory}} \\
\end{tabbing}
\end{center}
The \href{https://econ-ark.org/materials/BufferStockTheory?dashboard}{dashboard} lets users see consequences of alternative parameters in an interactive framework.} % end parbox{\textwidth}
\end{footnotesize}
\begin{authorsinfo}
\name{Contact: \href{mailto:ccarroll@jhu.edu}{\texttt{ccarroll@jhu.edu}}, Department of Economics, 590 Wyman Hall, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD 21218, \url{https://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll}, and National Bureau of Economic Research.}
\end{authorsinfo}
\newcommand{\thankstext}{
The paper's results \href{https://\owner.github.io/nbreproduce}{can be automatically reproduced} using the \href{https://econ-ark/HARK}{Econ-ARK/HARK} toolkit, which can be cited per our references (\cite{carroll_et_al-proc-scipy-2018}); for reference to the toolkit itself see \href{https://econ-ark.org/acknowledging/}{Acknowleding Econ-ARK}. Thanks to the \href{https://consumerfinance.gov}{Consumer Financial Protection Bureau} for funding the original creation of the \href{https://econ-ark.org}{Econ-ARK} toolkit; and to the \href{https://sloan.org}{Sloan Foundation} for funding Econ-ARK's \href{https://sloan.org/grant-detail/8071}{extensive further development} that brought it to the point where it could be used for this project. The toolkit can be cited with its digital object identifier, \href{https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.1001067}{10.5281/zenodo.1001067}, as is done in the paper's own references as \cite{carroll_et_al-proc-scipy-2018}. Thanks to Will Du, James Feigenbaum, Joseph Kaboski, Miles Kimball, Qingyin Ma, Misuzu Otsuka, Damiano Sandri, John Stachurski, Adam Szeidl, Alexis Akira Toda, Metin Uyanik, Mateo Vel\'asquez-Giraldo, Weifeng Wu, Jiaxiong Yao, and Xudong Zheng for comments on earlier versions of this paper, John Boyd for help in applying his weighted contraction mapping theorem, Ryoji Hiraguchi for extraordinary mathematical insight that improved the paper greatly, David Zervos for early guidance to the literature, and participants in a seminar at the Johns Hopkins University, a presentation at the 2009 meetings of the Society of Economic Dynamics for their insights, and at a presentation at the Australian National University.}
\ifthenelse{\boolean{Web}}{}{
\begin{minipage}{0.9\textwidth}
\tiny \thankstext
\end{minipage}
} % {Web}
{\titlepagefinish}
\hypertarget{Introduction}{}
\section{Introduction}\label{sec:intro}
In the presence of realistic transitory and permanent shocks to income \textit{a la}~\cite{friedmanATheory} and~\cite{muthOptimal}, only one further ingredient is required to construct a microeconomically testable model of consumption: A description of preferences. Zeldes~\citeyearpar{zeldesStochastic} was the first to calibrate a quantitatively plausible example; his paper spawned a literature showing that such models' predictions can match household life cycle data reasonably well, whether or not explicit liquidity constraints are imposed.\footnote{See~\cite{carrollBSLCPIH} or~\cite{gpLifeCycle} for arguments that models with only `natural' constraints (see below) match a wide variety of facts; for a model with explicit constraints that produces very similar results, see, e.g.,~\cite{Cagetti}.}
A connected literature in macroeconomic theory, starting with~\cite{bewleyPIH}, has derived limiting properties of related infinite-horizon problems, but only in models more complex than the case with just shocks and preferences. The extra complexity has been imposed because standard contraction mapping theorems (beginning with~\cite{bellmanDynamicProgramming} and including those building on Stokey et~al.~\citeyearpar{slpMethods}) cannot be applied when utility and/or marginal utility are unbounded. Many proof methods also rule out permanent shocks \textit{a la}~\cite{friedmanATheory},~\cite{muthOptimal}, and~\cite{zeldesStochastic}.\footnote{See \hyperlink{DiffFromLit}{the fuller discussion} at the end of Section~\ref{subsec:Setup}.}
This paper's first contribution is to articulate conditions under which the infinite-horizon Friedman-Muth(-Zeldes) problem (without complications like a consumption floor or liquidity constraints) defines a contraction mapping problem whose limit is sensible as the horizon approaches infinity. A \hyperlink{FVAC}{`Finite Value of Autarky Condition'} is mostly sufficient (the other imposed condition, the \hyperlink{WRIC}{`Weak Return Impatience Condition'},\footnote{This is a generalization of a condition in~\cite{mstIncFluct}.} is unlikely to bind). Because the infinite horizon solution is the limit of finite-horizon recursions, many intermediate results are also useful for solving finite-horizon problems.
But the paper's main theoretical contribution is to identify, for the infinite-horizon case, conditions under which `stable' values of the wealth-to-permanent-income ratio exist, either for individual consumers (a consumer's wealth can be predicted to move toward a `target' ratio) or for the aggregate (the economy as a whole moves toward a `balanced growth' equilibrium). The requirement for stability is always that the model's parameters satisfy a `Growth Impatience Condition' whose details depend on the quantity whose stability is of interest. A model that exhibits stability of either kind qualifies as a `buffer stock' model.\footnote{Such models are neither a subset nor a superset of~\cite{bewleyPIH} models. But closed economies in which capital results from saving and has declining marginal productivity are always `buffer stock' economies under some definition of that term, because capital accumulation causes interest rates to fall, which guarantees that a Growth Impatience Condition will hold in equilibrium (see below). The more interesting applications are to populations (or economies) whose marginal saving behavior does not determine the relevant interest rate, or in which the marginal product of capital does not fall as capital is accumulated (again, see below).}
\hypertarget{KMP}{} Even without a formal proof of its existence, buffer stock saving has been intuitively understood to underlie central quantitative results in heterogeneous agent macroeconomics; for example, the logic of target saving is central to the claim by~\cite{kmpHandbook} in the \textit{Handbook of Macroeconomics} that such models explain why, during the Great Recession, middle-class consumers cut their spending more than the poor or the rich. The theory below provides the rigorous basis for this claim: Learning that the future has become more uncertain does not change the urgent imperatives of the poor (their high $\uFunc^{\prime}(\cRat)$ means they --- optimally --- have little room to maneuver). And, increased labor income uncertainty does not much change the behavior of the rich because it poses little risk to their consumption. Only people in the middle have both the motivation and the wiggle-room to respond by reducing their spending.
Analytical derivations for the proofs also explain many other results familiar from the numerical literature.
The paper begins by defining sufficient conditions for the problem to define a useful (nondegenerate) limiting consumption function (and explains how the model relates to those previously considered). The conditions are interestingly parallel to those required for the \hyperlink{Factors-Defined-And-Compared}{liquidity constrained perfect foresight model}; that parallel is explored and explained. This analysis establishes limiting properties of the consumption function as resources approach infinity, and as they approach their lower bound; using these limits, the contraction mapping theorem is proven.
The next theoretical contribution demonstrates that a corresponding model with an `artificial' liquidity constraint (a model that prohibits borrowing by consumers who could certainly repay) is a limiting case of the model without constraints. The analytical appeal of the unconstrained model is that it is both mathematically convenient (e.g., the consumption function is twice continuously differentiable), and arbitraily close (cf.\ Section~\ref{sec:deatonIsLimit}) to less tractable models. The congenial environment makes the proof easier, and we define the analogous proposition as holding (in the limit) if it continues to hold as the horizon extends to infinity.
In proving the remaining theorems, the \hyperlink{AnalysisoftheConvergedConsumptionFunction}{next section} examines the key properties of the model. First, as \hyperlink{LimitsAsmtToInfty}{cash approaches infinity} the expected growth rate of consumption and the marginal propensity to consume (MPC) converge to their values in the perfect foresight case. Second, as \hyperlink{LimitsAsmtToZero}{cash approaches zero} the expected growth rate of consumption approaches infinity, and the MPC approaches a simple analytical limit. Next, the central theorems articulate conditions under which different measures of `growth impatience' imply useful conclusions about points of stability (`target' or `balanced growth' points).
The final section elaborates the conditions under which, even with a fixed aggregate interest rate that differs from the time preference rate, a small open economy populated by buffer stock consumers has a balanced growth equilibrium in which growth rates of consumption, income, and wealth match the exogenous growth rate of permanent income (equivalent, here, to productivity growth). In the terms of~\cite{schmitt2003closing}, buffer stock saving is an appealing method of `closing' a small open economy model, because it requires no ad-hoc assumptions. Not even liquidity constraints.\footnote{The paper's insights are instantiated in the \href{https://econ-ark.org}{Econ-ARK} toolkit, whose \href{https://hark.readthedocs.io/en/stable/reference/ConsumptionSaving/ConsIndShockModel.html}{buffer stock saving module} flags parametric choices under which a problem is degenerate or under which stable ratios of wealth to income may not exist.}
\hypertarget{The-Problem}{}
\section{The Problem}
\subsection{Setup}\label{subsec:Setup}
The infinite horizon solution is the (limiting) first-period solution to a sequence of finite-horizon problems as the horizon (the last period of life) becomes arbitrarily distant.
That is, for the value function, fixing a terminal date $T$, we are interested in the term $\vLevBF_{T-n}$ in the sequence of value functions $\{\vLevBF_{T},\vLevBF_{T-1},\ldots,\vLevBF_{T-n}\}$. We will say that the problem has a `nondegenerate' infinite horizon solution if, corresponding to that $\vLevBF$, as $n \uparrow \infty$ there is a limiting consumption function $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat) = \lim_{n \uparrow \infty} \cFunc_{T-n}$ which is neither $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)=0$ everywhere (for all $\mRat$) nor $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\infty$ everywhere.
Concretely, a consumer born $n$ periods before date $T$ solves the problem
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/supfn}
\begin{align*}% \label{eq:supfn}
\vLevBF_{T-n} & = \max~ \Ex_{t}\left[\sum_{i=0}^{n} \DiscFac^{i} \uFunc(\cLevBF_{t+i})\right]
\end{align*}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\LtxDir\EqDir/supfn}
where the Constant Relative Risk Aversion (CRRA) utility function
\begin{align}
\uFunc(\bullet)=\bullet^{1-\CRRA}/(1-\CRRA) \label{eq:crrautil}
\end{align}
exhibits relative risk aversion $\CRRA > 1$.\footnote{The main
results also hold for logarithmic utility which is the limit as
$\CRRA \rightarrow 1$ but incorporating the logarithmic special case
in the proofs is omitted because it would be cumbersome.} The consumer's initial condition is
defined by market resources $\mLevBF_{t}$ and permanent noncapital income $\pLevBF_{t}$, which
both are positive,
\begin{align}
\{\pLevBF_{t},\mLevBF_{t}\} & \in (0,\infty) \label{eq:pLevBFandmLevBFgt0},
\end{align}
and the consumer cannot die in debt,
\begin{align}
\cLevBF_{T} & \leq \mLevBF_{T} \label{eq:NoDebtAtDeath}.
\end{align}
\hypertarget{checkRestrictions}{}
In the usual treatment, a dynamic budget constraint (DBC) incorporates
several elements that jointly determine next period's $\mLevBF$ (given this
period's choices); for the detailed analysis here, it will be useful to
disarticulate and describe every step:\hypertarget{DBCParts}{}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/DBCparts}
\begin{align}
\aLevBF_{t} & = \mLevBF_{t}-\cLevBF_{t} \label{eq:DBCparts} \\
\kLevBF_{t+1} & = \aLevBF_{t} \notag \\
\bLevBF_{t+1} & = \kLevBF_{t} \Rfree \notag \\
\pLevBF_{t+1} & = \pLevBF_{t} \underbrace{\PGro\pShk_{t+1}}_{\equiv \PGro_{t+1}} \notag \\
\mLevBF_{t+1} & = \bLevBF_{t+1} +\pLevBF_{t+1}\tShkAll_{t+1}, \notag
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\LtxDir\EqDir/DBCparts}
where $\aLevBF_{t}$ indicates the consumer's assets at the end of period $t$, which translate one-for-one into capital $\kLevBF_{t+1}$ at the beginning of the next period, which (before the consumption choice) grows by a fixed interest factor $\Rfree =(1+\rfree)$, so that $\bLevBF_{t+1}$ is the consumer's financial (`bank') balances before next period's consumption choice;\footnote{Allowing a stochastic interest factor is straightforward but adds little insight for our purposes; however, see~\cite{benhabibWealth},~\cite{maTodaRich}, and~\cite{mstIncFluct} for the implications of capital income risk for the distribution of wealth and other interesting questions not considered here.} $\mLevBF_{t+1}$ (`market resources') is the sum of financial wealth $\bLevBF_{t+1}$ and noncapital income $\pLevBF_{t+1}\tShkAll_{t+1}$ (permanent noncapital income $\pLevBF_{t+1}$ multiplied by a mean-one iid transitory income shock factor $\tShkAll_{t+1}$; transitory shocks are assumed to satisfy $\Ex_{t}[{\tShkAll}_{t+n}]=1~\forall~n\geq 1$). Permanent noncapital income in $t+1$ is equal to its previous value, multiplied by a growth factor $\PGro$, modified by a mean-one iid shock $\pShk_{t+1}$, $\Ex_{t}[{\pShk}_{t+n}]=1~\forall~n \geq 1$ satisfying $\pShk \in [\ushort{\pShk},\bar{\pShk}]$ for $0 < \ushort{\pShk} \leq 1 \leq \bar{\pShk} < \infty$ (and $\ushort{\pShk}=\bar{\pShk}=1$ is the degenerate case with no permanent shocks).
Following~\cite{zeldesStochastic}, in future periods $t+n ~\forall~ n \geq 1$ there is a small probability $\pZero$ that income will be zero (a `zero-income event'),
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/tShkDef}
\begin{equation}
\tShkAll _{t+n}=
\begin{cases}
0\phantom{_{t+1}/\pNotZero} & \text{with probability $\pZero>0$} \\
\tShkEmp_{t+n}/\pNotZero & \text{with probability $\pNotZero $} % \equiv (1-\pZero)
\end{cases} \label{eq:tShkDef}
\end{equation}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\LtxDir\EqDir/tShkDef}
where $\tShkEmp_{t+n}$ is an iid mean-one random variable
($\Ex_{t}[{\tShkEmp}_{t+n}]=1~\forall~n>0$)
whose distribution satisfies $\tShkEmp \in \lbrack \ushort{\tShkEmp},\bar{\tShkEmp}\rbrack$
where $0<\ushort{\tShkEmp} \leq 1 \leq \bar{\tShkEmp}<\infty$.\footnote{\cite{rabaultBorrowing} and~\cite{lsIncFluct} analyze cases where the shock processes have unbounded support.} Call the cumulative
distribution functions $\CDF_{\pShk}$ and $\CDF_{\tShkEmp}$ (where $\CDF_{\tShkAll}$
is derived trivially from~\eqref{eq:tShkDef} and $\CDF_{\tShkEmp}$). For quick identification in tables and graphs, we will call this the `Friedman/Muth' model because it is a specific implementation of the~\cite{friedmanATheory} model as interpreted by~\cite{muthOptimal}.
\hypertarget{PDV}{}
The model looks more special than it is. In particular, a positive probability of zero-income events may seem objectionable (despite empirical support).\footnote{We calibrate this probability to 0.005 to match data from the Panel Study of Income Dynamics (\cite{carrollBrookings}).} But a model with a nonzero minimum value of $\tShkAll$ (motivated, say, by the existence of unemployment insurance) can be redefined by capitalizing the PDV of minimum income into current market assets,\footnote{So long as unemployment benefits are proportional to $\pLevBF_{t}$; see the discussion in Section~\ref{sec:discussConvergence}.} transforming that model back into this one. And no key results would change if the transitory shocks were persistent but mean-reverting, instead of IID.\@ Also, the assumption of a positive point mass for the worst realization of the transitory shock is inessential, but simplifies the proofs and is a powerful aid to intuition.%\footnote{A positive density over a positive interval above the lower bound would work instead but would be cumbersome.}
\hypertarget{DiffFromLit}{} This model differs from Bewley's~\citeyearpar{bewleyPIH} classic formulation in several ways. The CRRA utility function does not satisfy Bewley's assumption that $\uFunc(0)$ is well-defined, or that $\uP(0)$ is well defined and finite; indeed, neither the value function nor the marginal value function will be bounded. It differs from Schectman and Escudero~\citeyearpar{seIncFluct} in that they impose liquidity constraints and positive minimum income. It differs from both of these in that it permits permanent growth in income, and also permanent shocks to income, which a large empirical literature finds to be of dominant importance in micro data.\footnote{MaCurdy~\citeyearpar{macurdyTimeseries}; Abowd and Card~\citeyearpar{acCovariance}; Carroll and Samwick~\citeyearpar{csNature}; Jappelli and Pistaferri~\citeyearpar{jpCins}. Much of the literature instead incorporates highly `persistent' but not completely permanent shocks, but~\cite{dhmImproving} show that when measurement problems are handled correctly data yields serial correlation coefficients $0.98-1.00$; and~\cite{dmHowMuch} suggests that survey data support the same conclusion.} It differs from Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr} because liquidity constraints are absent; there are separate transitory and permanent shocks (\textit{a la}~\cite{muthOptimal}); and the transitory shocks here can occasionally cause income to reach zero.%\footnote{Below it will become clear that the Deaton model is a particular limit of this paper's model.}
It differs from models found in Stokey et.\ al.~\citeyearpar{slpMethods} because neither liquidity constraints nor bounds on utility or marginal utility are imposed.\footnote{Similar restrictions are made in the well known papers by Scheinkman and Weiss~\citeyearpar{scheinkman&weiss:borrowing}, Clarida~\citeyearpar{claridaErgodic}, and~\cite{cwcUnderUncert}. See~\cite{tocheUrisk} for an elegant analysis of a related but simpler continuous-time model.}$^{,}$\footnote{\cite{asHomogeneous} relaxed the bounds on the return function, but they address only the deterministic case.}~\cite{lsIncFluct} show how to allow unbounded returns by using policy function iteration, but also impose constraints.
The paper with perhaps the most in common is~\cite{mstIncFluct}, henceforth MST, who establish the existence and uniqueness of a solution to a general income fluctuation problem in a Markovian setting. The most important differences are that MST impose liquidity constraints, assume that $\uFunc^{\prime}(0)=0$, and that expected marginal utility of income is finite ($\Ex[\uFunc^{\prime}(Y)]<\infty)$. These assumptions are not consistent with the combination of CRRA utility and income dynamics used here, whose joint properties are key to the results.\footnote{The incorporation of permanent shocks rules out application of the tools of~\cite{mnUnique}, who followed and corrected an error in the fundamental work on the local contraction mapping method developed in~\cite{rrExistence}.\@~\cite{mvExistence} provide a correction to~\cite{rrExistence}, that works under easier conditions to verify, but only addresses the deterministic case.}
\hypertarget{The-Problem-Can-Be-Rewritten-in-Ratio-Form}{}
\hypertarget{The-Problem-Can-Be-Normalized-By-Permanent-Income}{}
\subsection{The Problem Can Be Normalized By Permanent Income}\label{subsec:ratio}
We establish a bit more notation by reviewing the familiar result that in such problems (CRRA utility, permanent shocks) the number of states can be reduced from two ($\mLevBF$ and $\pLevBF$) to one $(\mRat = \mLevBF/\pLevBF)$. Value in the last period is $\uFunc(\mLevBF_{T})$; using (in the last line in~\eqref{eq:vBold} below) the fact that for our CRRA utility function, $\uFunc(xy) = x^{1-\CRRA}\uFunc(y)$, and generically defining nonbold variables as the boldface counterpart normalized by $\pLevBF_{t}$ (as with $\mRat=\mLevBF/\pLevBF$), consider the problem in the second-to-last period,
\begin{align}
\vLevBF_{T-1}(\mLevBF_{T-1},\pLevBF_{T-1}) & =
\max_{\cLevBF_{T-1}}~ \uFunc(\cLevBF_{T-1}) +\DiscFac \Ex_{T-1} [ \uFunc(\mLevBF_{T})]
\notag \\
& = \max_{\cRat_{T-1}}~
\uFunc(\pLevBF_{T-1}\cRat_{T-1}) + \DiscFac \Ex_{T-1} [\uFunc(\pLevBF_{T}{\mRat}
_{T})] \notag \\
& = \pLevBF_{T-1}^{1-\CRRA}
\left\{\max_{\cRat_{T-1}}~ \uFunc(c_{T-1}) + \DiscFac \Ex_{T-1} [ \uFunc( {\PGro}_{T}
{\mRat}_{T}) ] \right\}. \label{eq:vBold}
\end{align}
\hypertarget{The-Related-Problem}{}
Now, in a one-time deviation from the notational convention established in the last sentence, define nonbold `normalized value' not as $\vLevBF_{t}/\pLevBF_{t}$ but as $\vFunc_{t} = \vLevBF_{t}/\pLevBF_{t}^{1-\CRRA}$, because this allows us to exploit features of the related problem,
\begin{align}
\vFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}) & = \max_{{\{\cFunc\}}_{t}^{T}}~ \uFunc(\cFunc_{t}) +\DiscFac \Ex_{t}[\PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}\vFunc_{t+1}({\mRat}_{t+1})] \notag \\
& \mbox{s.t.} \label{eq:veqn}
\\ {\aRat}_{t} & = \mRat_{t}-c_{t} \notag
\\ {\kRat}_{t+1} & = \aRat_{t}/\PGro_{t+1} \notag
\\ {\bRat}_{t+1} & = {\kRat}_{t+1}\Rfree = (\Rfree/\PGro_{t+1})\aRat_{t} ~ = ~ \Rnorm_{t+1}\aRat_{t} \notag
\\ \mRat_{t+1} & = \bRat_{t+1}+\tShkAll_{t+1} \notag, %
\end{align}
where $\Rnorm_{t+1}\equiv (\Rfree/\PGro_{t+1})$ is a `permanent-income-growth-normalized' return factor, and the reformulated problem's first order condition is\footnote{Leaving aside their assumptions about the marginal utility function and liquidity constraints, it is tempting to view this as a special case of the model of MST, with our $\Rnorm_{t+1}=\Rfree/\PGro_{t+1}$ (defined below equation~\eqref{eq:veqn}) corresponding to their stochastic rate of return on capital and the {\FVAF} $\DiscFac \PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}$ defined below~\eqref{eq:FVAC} corresponding to their stochastic discount factor. A caveat is that, here, $\Rnorm_{t+1}$ and the modified discount factor are intimately (through $\PGro_{t+1}$), which has profound effects. It would be interesting, and should not be too difficult, to examine the case with independent shocks to the rate of return and productivity growth.}
\begin{align}
c_{t}^{-\CRRA} & = \Rfree \DiscFac \Ex_{t}[ {\PGro}_{t+1}^{-\CRRA} {\cRat}
_{t+1}^{-\CRRA}]. \label{eq:scaledeuler}
%\\ & = \DiscFac \Ex_{t}[ \Rnorm_{t+1} {\PGro}_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA} {\cRat}
% _{t+1}^{-\CRRA}]. \label{eq:scaledeuler2}
\end{align}
Since $\vFunc_{T}(\mRat_{T}) = \uFunc(\mRat_{T})$, defining $\vFunc_{T-1}(\mRat_{T-1})$ from~\eqref{eq:veqn}, we obtain
\begin{align*}
\vLevBF_{T-1}(\mLevBF_{T-1},\pLevBF_{T-1}) & = \pLevBF_{T-1}^{1-\CRRA} \vFunc_{T-1}(\underbrace{\mLevBF_{T-1}/\pLevBF_{T-1}}_{=\mRat_{T-1}}).
\end{align*}
This logic induces to earlier periods; if we solve the
normalized one-state-variable problem~\eqref{eq:veqn}, we
will have solutions to the original problem for any $t<T$
from:
\begin{align*}
\vLevBF_{t}(\mLevBF_{t},\pLevBF_{t}) & = \pLevBF_{t}^{1-\CRRA}\vFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}),
\\ \cLevBF_{t}(\mLevBF_{t},\pLevBF_{t}) & = \pLevBF_{t}\cFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}).
\end{align*}
\hypertarget{Definition-of-a-Nondegenerate-Solution}{}
\subsection{Definition of a Nondegenerate Solution}
The problem has a nondegenerate solution if as the horizon $n$ gets arbitrarily large the solution in the first period of life $\usual{\cFunc}_{T-n}(\mRat)$ gets arbitrarily close to a limiting $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)$:
\begin{align}
\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat) & \equiv \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \cFunc_{T-n}(\mRat)
\end{align}
that satisfies
\begin{align}
0 & < \usual{\cFunc}(\mRat) < \infty
\end{align}
for every $0 < \mRat < \infty$.% (`Degenerate' limits will be cases where the limiting consumption function is $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)=0$ or $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\infty$; below when we say a `solution exists' we will always mean `a nondegenerate solution.')
\hypertarget{Perfect-Foresight-Benchmarks}{}
\subsection{Perfect Foresight Benchmarks}
The familiar analytical solution to the perfect foresight model, obtained by setting $\pZero=0$ and $\ushort{\tShkEmp}=\bar{\tShkEmp}=\ushort{\pShk}=\bar{\pShk}=1$, allows us to define some remaining notation and terminology.
\hypertarget{Human-Wealth}{}
\subsubsection{Human Wealth}
The dynamic budget constraint, strictly positive marginal utility, and the can't-die-in-debt condition~\eqref{eq:NoDebtAtDeath} imply an exactly-holding intertemporal budget constraint (IBC):
\begin{align}
\mathrm{PDV}_{t}(\cLevBF) & = \overbrace{\mLevBF_{t}-\pLevBF_{t}}^{\bLevBF_{t}}+\overbrace{\mathrm{PDV}_{t}(\pLevBF)}^{\hLevBF_{t}}, \label{eq:IBCFinite}
\end{align} \hypertarget{FHWF}{}
where $\bLevBF$ is nonhuman wealth, and with a constant $\Rnorm \equiv \Rfree/\PGro$ `human wealth' is
\begin{align}
\hLevBF_{t} & = \pLevBF_{t}+\Rnorm^{-1} \pLevBF_{t} + \Rnorm^{-2} \pLevBF_{t} + \cdots + \Rnorm^{t-T} \pLevBF_{t} \notag
\\ & = \underbrace{\left(\frac{1-\Rnorm^{-(T-t+1)}}{1-\Rnorm^{-1}}\right)}_{\equiv \hRat_{t}}\pLevBF_{t} \label{eq:HDef}.
\end{align}\hypertarget{FHWC}{}
For $\hRat \equiv \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \hRat_{T-n}$ to be finite, need the Finite Human Wealth Condition (`\FHWC'):
\begin{align}
\underbrace{\PGro/\Rfree}_{\equiv \Rnorm^{-1}} & < 1 \label{eq:FHWC}.
\end{align}
Intuitively, finite human wealth requires a growth rate of (noncapital) income smaller than the interest rate at which that income is being discounted.
\hypertarget{Unconstrained-Solution}{}\hypertarget{PF-Unconstrained-Solution}{}
\subsubsection{When Does the Perfect Foresight Unconstrained Solution Exist?}\label{subsec:PFUncon}
\hypertarget{APF}{}\hypertarget{AIC}{}
Without constraints, the consumption Euler equation always holds; with $\uP(\cLevBF)=\cLevBF^{-\CRRA}$, \hypertarget{Pat}{}
\begin{align}
\cLevBF_{t+1}/\cLevBF_{t} & = {(\Rfree\DiscFac)}^{1/\CRRA} \equiv \Pat \label{eq:Pat}
\end{align}
where the archaic letter \href{https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Thorn_(letter)}{`thorn'} represents what we will call the `Absolute Patience Factor' or APF:\@
\begin{align}
\Pat & = {(\Rfree\DiscFac)}^{1/\CRRA} \label{eq:APF}.
\end{align}
$\Pat$ captures `patience' because, if the `absolute impatience condition' (\AIC) holds,\footnote{Impatience conditions have figured in intertemporal optimization problems since the beginning, e.g.\ in~\cite{ramseySave}. These issues are so central that it would be hopeless to attempt to cite conditions in every other paper that correspond to conditions named and briefly exposited here. I make no claim to novelty for any condition aside from those implicated in my theorems, whose parallels \textit{will} be articulated.}
\begin{align}
\label{eq:AIC}
\Pat & < 1,
\end{align}
the consumer's level of spending will be too large to sustain indefinitely. We call such a consumer `absolutely impatient.'\hypertarget{RPF}{}
A `Return Patience Factor' (RPF) relates absolute patience to the return factor:
\begin{align}
\PatR & \equiv {\Pat}/\Rfree \label{eq:PatR}
\end{align}
and since consumption is growing by $\Pat$ but discounted by $\Rfree$:
\begin{align}
\mathrm{PDV}_{t}(\cLevBF) & = \left(\frac{1-\PatR^{T-t+1}}{1-\PatR}\right)\cLevBF_{t}
\end{align}
from which the IBC~\eqref{eq:IBCFinite} implies
\begin{align}
\cLevBF_{t} & = \overbrace{\left(\frac{1-\PatR}{1-\PatR^{T-t+1}}\right)}^{\equiv \MinMPC_{t}}
(\bLevBF_{t}+\hLevBF_{t}) \label{eq:WDef}
\end{align}
which defines a normalized finite-horizon perfect foresight consumption function
\begin{align}
\bar{\cFunc}_{T-n}(\mRat_{T-n}) & = (\overbrace{\mRat_{T-n}-1}^{
\equiv\bRat_{T-n}}+\hRat_{T-n})\MinMPC_{T-n}
\end{align}
where $\MinMPC_{t}$ is the marginal propensity to consume (MPC) --- it answers the
question `if the consumer had an extra unit of resources, how much more spending would occur.' \hypertarget{RIC}{}
($\bar{\cFunc}$'s overbar signfies that $\bar{\cFunc}$ will be an upper bound as we modify the problem to incorporate constraints and uncertainty; analogously, $\MinMPC$ is a lower bound for the MPC).
The denominator of~\eqref{eq:WDef} is the reason that, for $\underbar{\MPC}$ to be strictly positive as $n=T-t$ goes to infinity, we must impose the Return Impatience Condition (\RIC):
\begin{align}
\PatR & < 1 \label{eq:RIC},
\end{align}
so that
\begin{align}
0 < \MinMPC & \equiv 1-\PatR = \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \MinMPC_{T-n} \label{eq:MinMPCDef}
.
\end{align}
The {\RIC} thus implies that the consumer cannot be so pathologically patient as to wish, in the limit as the horizon approaches infinity, to spend nothing today out of an increase in current wealth (the {\RIC} rules out the degenerate limiting solution $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)=0$). We call a consumer who satisfies the {\RIC} `return impatient.'
Given that the {\RIC}~holds, and (as before) defining limiting objects by the absence of a time subscript, the limiting upper bound consumption function will be
\begin{align}\label{eq:cFuncPFUnc}
\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat) & = (\mRat+\hRat-1)\MinMPC,
\end{align}
and so in order to rule out the degenerate limiting
solution $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat) = \infty$ we need $\hRat$ to be finite; that is, we
must impose the Finite Human Wealth Condition~\eqref{eq:FHWC}.
\hypertarget{ValuePFAnalytical}{}
\hypertarget{Autarky-Value-PF}{}
Because $\uFunc(xy) = x^{1-\CRRA}\uFunc(y)$ the value the consumer would achieve by spending permanent income $\pLevBF$ in every period is:
\begin{align}
\vLevBF_{t}^{\text{autarky}} & = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})+\DiscFac \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t}\PGro)+\DiscFac^{2} \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t} \PGro^{2})+\ldots \label{eq:ValuePFAnalyticalAutarky}
\\ & = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(1+\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}+{(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA})}^{2}+\ldots\right) \notag
\\ & = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(\frac{1-{(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA})}^{T-t+1}}{1-\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}}\right) \notag
\end{align}
which (for $\PGro>0$) asymptotes to a finite number as $n=T-t$ approaches $+\infty$ if any of these equivalent conditions holds:
\begin{align}
\overbrace{\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA} }^{\equiv \DiscAlt} & < 1 \nonumber
\\ \DiscFac \Rfree \PGro^{-\CRRA} & < \Rfree/\PGro \label{eq:PFFVAC}
\\ \PatR & < {(\PGro/\Rfree)}^{1-1/\CRRA}, \nonumber
\end{align}
where we call $\DiscAlt$\footnote{This is another kind of discount factor, so we use the Hebrew `bet' which is a cognate of the Greek `beta'.} the `Perfect Foresight Value Of Autarky Factor' ({\PFVAF}), and the variants of~\eqref{eq:PFFVAC} constitute alternative versions of the Perfect Foresight Finite Value of Autarky Condition, \PFFVAC; they guarantee that a consumer who always spends all permanent income `has finite autarky value' (in the perfect foresight case).\footnote{This is related to the key impatience condition in~\cite{asHomogeneous}.} % chktex 13
If the {\FHWC} is satisfied, the {\PFFVAC} implies that the {\RIC} is satisfied.\footnote{Divide both sides of the second inequality in~\eqref{eq:PFFVAC} by $\Rfree$:
\begin{align}
\Pat/\Rfree & < {(\PGro/\Rfree)}^{1-1/\CRRA} \label{eq:FHWCandPFFVACimplyRIC}
\end{align}
and {\FHWC} $\Rightarrow$ the RHS is $< 1$ because $(\PGro/\Rfree) < 1$ (and the RHS is raised to a positive power (because $\CRRA>1$)).} Likewise, if the {\FHWC} and the {\GIC} are both satisfied, {\PFFVAC} follows:
\begin{align}
\Pat & < \PGro < \Rfree \notag
\\ \PatR & < \PGro/\Rfree < {(\PGro/\Rfree)}^{1-1/\CRRA} < 1\label{eq:GICandFHWCimplyPFFVAC}
\end{align}
(the last line holds because {\FHWC} $\Rightarrow 0 \leq (\PGro/\Rfree) < 1$ and $\CRRA > 1 \Rightarrow 0 < 1-1/\CRRA < 1$).
The first panel of Table~\ref{table:Required} summarizes: The PF-Unconstrained model has a nondegenerate limiting solution if we impose the {\RIC} and {\FHWC} (these conditions are necessary as well as sufficient). Together the {\PFFVAC} and the {\FHWC} imply the {\RIC}, so {\PFFVAC} and {\FHWC} are jointly sufficient. If we impose the {\GIC} and the {\FHWC}, both the {\PFFVAC} and the {\RIC} follow, so {\GIC}+{\FHWC} are also sufficient. But there are circumstances under which the {\RIC} and {\FHWC} can hold while the {\PFFVAC} fails (which we write \cncl{\PFFVAC}). For example, if $\PGro=0$, the problem is a standard `cake-eating' problem with a nondegenerate solution under the {\RIC}.% chktex 10
Perhaps more useful than prose or a table, the relations of the conditions for the unconstrained perfect foresight case are presented diagrammatically in Figure~\ref{fig:RelatePFGICFHWCRICPFFVAC}. Each node represents a quantity considered in the foregoing analysis. The arrow associated with each inequality reflects the imposition of that condition. For example, one way we wrote the {\PFFVAC} in equation~\eqref{eq:PFFVAC} is $\Pat < \Rfree^{1/\CRRA} \PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}$, so imposition of the {\PFFVAC} is captured by the diagonal arrow connecting $\Pat$ and $\Rfree^{1/\CRRA}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}$. Traversing the boundary of the diagram clockwise starting at $\Pat$ involves imposing first the {\GICRaw} then the {\FHWC}, and the consequent arrival at the bottom right node tells us that these two conditions jointly imply that the {\PFFVAC} holds. Reversal of a condition reverses the arrow's direction; so, for example, the bottom-most arrow going from $\Rfree$ to $\Rfree^{1/\CRRA}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}$ imposes {\cncl{\FHWC}}; but we can cancel the cancellation and reverse the arrow. This would allow us to traverse the diagram in a clockwise direction from $\Pat$ to $\Rfree$, revealing that imposition of {\GICRaw} and {\FHWC} (and, redundantly, {\FHWC} again) let us conclude that the {\RIC} holds because the starting point is $\Pat$ and the endpoint is $\Rfree$. (Consult Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxConditionDiagrams} for a detailed exposition of diagrams of this type).
\providecommand{\figName}{RelatePFGICFHWCRICPFFVAC} % Allows generic definition of hypertargets based on title of figure
\providecommand{\figFile}{\figName} % and on filename
%\hypertarget{\figFile}{}
\hypertarget{\figName}{}
\input{\FigDir/\figName} % Read in the tex to generate the figure
\hypertarget{PF-Constrained-Solution}{}
\hypertarget{Constrained-Solution}{}
\subsubsection{PF Constrained Solution Exists Under~\texorpdfstring{{\RIC}}{RIC} or Under~\texorpdfstring{\{\cncl{\RIC},\GICRaw\}}{RIC-Fails,GIC}}\label{subsec:PFCon}
We next sketch the perfect foresight constrained solution because it is a useful benchmark (and limit) for the unconstrained problem with uncertainty which is our ultimate interest.
If a liquidity constraint requiring $\bRat \geq 0$ is ever to be relevant, it must be relevant at the lowest possible level of market resources, $\mRat_{t}=1$, defined by the lower bound for entering the period, $\bRat_{t}=0$ (if it were relevant at any higher point, it would certainly be relevant at this point). The constraint is `relevant' if it prevents the choice that would otherwise be optimal; at $\mRat_{t}=1$ the constraint is relevant if the marginal utility from spending all of today's resources $c_{t}=m_{t}=1$, exceeds the marginal utility from doing the same thing next period, $\cRat_{t+1}=1$; that is, if such choices would violate the Euler equation~\eqref{eq:scaledeuler}:
\begin{align}
1^{-\CRRA} & > \Rfree \DiscFac \PGro^{-\CRRA}1^{-\CRRA} \label{eq:LiqConstrBinds}.
\end{align}
\hypertarget{GPFRaw}{}
\hypertarget{GICRaw}{}
By analogy to the \RPF, we therefore define a `growth patience factor' (\GPFRaw) as
\begin{align}
\PatPGro & = {\Pat}/\PGro, \label{eq:GPFRaw}
\end{align}
and define a `growth impatience condition' (\GICRaw)
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/GICRaw}
\begin{align}
\PatPGro & < 1 \label{eq:GICRaw}
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\LtxDir\EqDir/GICRaw}
which is equivalent to~\eqref{eq:LiqConstrBinds} (exponentiate both
sides by $1/\CRRA$).
We now examine implications of possible configurations of the conditions.
\textit{\cncl{\GICRaw} and {\RIC}.} If the {\GICRaw} fails but the {\RIC}~\eqref{eq:RIC} holds, Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxLiqConstr} shows that, for some $0 < \mRat_{\#} < 1$, an unconstrained consumer behaving according to~\eqref{eq:cFuncPFUnc} would choose $\cRat < \mRat$ for all $\mRat > \mRat_{\#}$. In this case the solution to the constrained consumer's problem is simple: For any $\mRat \geq \mRat_{\#}$ the constraint does not bind (and will never bind in the future); for such $\mRat$ the constrained consumption function is identical to the unconstrained one. If the consumer were somehow\footnote{``Somehow'' because $\mRat<1$ could only be obtained by entering the period with $\bRat < 0$ which the constraint forbids.} to arrive at an $\mRat < \mRat_{\#} < 1$ the constraint would bind and the consumer would consume $\cRat=\mRat$. Using the $\constr{\bullet}$ accent for the version of a function $\bullet$ in the presence of constraints (and recalling that $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)$ is the unconstrained perfect foresight solution):
\begin{equation}
\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)=
\begin{cases}
\mRat & \text{if $\mRat < \mRat_{\#}$} \\
\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat) & \text{if $\mRat \geq \mRat_{\#}$.}
\end{cases}
\end{equation}
\textit{{\GICRaw} and {\RIC}.} More useful is the case where the return impatience and {\GIC} conditions both hold. In this case Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxLiqConstr} shows that the limiting constrained consumption function is piecewise linear, with $\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\mRat$ up to a first `kink point' at $\mRat_{\#}^{1}>1$, and with discrete declines in the MPC at a set of kink points $\{\mRat_{\#}^{1},\mRat_{\#}^{2},\ldots\}$. As $\mRat \uparrow \infty$ the constrained consumption function $\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)$ becomes arbitrarily close to the unconstrained $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)$, and the marginal propensity to consume function $\constr{\MPCFunc}(\mRat) \equiv \constr{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat)$ limits to $\MinMPC$.\footnote{See~\cite{chkLiqConstr} for details.} Similarly, the value function $\constr{\vFunc}(\mRat)$ is nondegenerate and limits into the value function of the unconstrained consumer.
This logic holds even when the finite human wealth condition fails (\cncl{\FHWC}), because the constraint prevents the (limiting) consumer\footnote{That is, one obeying $\cFunc(\mRat) = \lim_{n \uparrow \infty} \cFunc_{T-n}(\mRat)$.} from borrowing against unbounded human wealth to finance unbounded current consumption. Under these circumstances, the consumer who starts with any $\bRat_{t} > 1$ will, over time, run those resources down so that by some finite number of periods $\tau$ in the future the consumer will reach $\bRat_{t+\tau} = 0$, and thereafter will set $\cLevBF = \pLevBF$ for eternity (which the {\PFFVAC} says yields finite value). Using the same steps as for equation~\eqref{eq:ValuePFAnalyticalAutarky}, value of the interim program is also finite: \hypertarget{PFFVAC}{} \hypertarget{PFVAF}{}
\begin{align*}
\vLevBF_{t+\tau} % & = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t+\tau})\left(1+\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}+(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA})^{2}+\ldots\right)
& = \PGro^{\tau(1-\CRRA)} \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(\frac{1-{(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA})}^{T-(t+\tau)+1}}{1-\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}}\right).
\end{align*}
%Note that the last version of the \PFFVAC~in~\eqref{eq:PFFVAC} implies the \GICRaw~$\PatPGro < 1$ whenever \cncl{\FHWC} ($\Rfree < \PGro$) holds.
So, if \cncl{\FHWC}, the limiting consumer's value for any finite $\mRat$ will be the sum of two finite numbers: The component due to the unconstrained consumption choice made over the finite horizon leading up to $\bRat_{t+\tau} = 0$, and the finite component due to the value of consuming all $\pLevBF_{t+\tau}$ thereafter.
\hypertarget{RICandFHWCFail}{} \textit{{\GICRaw} and {\cncl{\RIC}}}. The most peculiar possibility occurs when the \RIC~fails. Under these circumstances the \FHWC~must also fail (Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxLiqConstr}), and the constrained consumption function is nondegenerate. (See appendix Figure~\ref{fig:PFGICHoldsFHWCFailsRICFails} for a numerical example). While it is true that $\lim_{m \uparrow \infty} \constr{\MPCFunc}(\mRat) = 0$, nevertheless the limiting constrained consumption function $\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)$ is strictly positive and strictly increasing in $\mRat$. This result interestingly reconciles the conflicting intuitions from the unconstrained case, where \cncl{\RIC} would suggest a degenerate limit of $\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)=0$ while \cncl{\FHWC} would suggest a degenerate limit of $\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\infty$.
%\hypertarget{RelatePFGICFHWCRICPFFVACText}{}
Tables~\ref{table:Comparison} and~\ref{table:Required} (and appendix table~\ref{table:LiqConstrScenarios}) codify.
We now examine the case with uncertainty but without constraints, which will turn out to be a close parallel to the model with constraints but without uncertainty.
\hypertarget{Uncertainty-Modified-Conditions}{}
\subsection{Uncertainty-Modified Conditions}\label{subsec:UncertaintyModifiedConditions}
\subsubsection{Impatience}
When uncertainty is introduced, the expectation of beginning-of-period bank balances $\bRat_{t+1}$ can be rewritten as:
\begin{align}
\Ex_{t}[\bRat_{t+1}] & = \aRat_{t}\Ex_{t}[(\Rfree/\PGro_{t+1})] = \aRat_{t}(\Rfree/\PGro)\Ex_{t}[\pShk_{t+1}^{-1}] \label{eq:EbRat}
\end{align}
where Jensen's inequality guarantees that the expectation of the inverse of the permanent shock is greater than one. It will be convenient to define\hypertarget{InvEpShkInv}{}
\begin{align}
\InvEpShkInv & \equiv {(\EpShkInv)}^{-1} \label{eq:InvEpShkInv}
\end{align}
which satisfies $\InvEpShkInv < 1$ (thanks again to Mr.\ Jensen), so we can define
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/PGroAdj}
\begin{align}
\PGroAdj & \equiv \PGro \InvEpShkInv < \PGro \label{eq:PGroAdj}
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\LtxDir\EqDir/PGroAdj}
which allows us to write uncertainty-adjusted versions of equations and conditions in a manner exactly parallel to those for the perfect foresight case; for example, we define a normalized Growth Patience Factor (GPF-Nrm):
\hypertarget{GICNrm}{}\hypertarget{GICNrmI}{}\hypertarget{PermGroAdj}{}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/PatPGroAdj}
\begin{align}
\PatPGroAdj & = \Pat/\PGroAdj = \Ex[\Pat/(\PGro\pShk)] \label{eq:GPFNrm}
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\LtxDir\EqDir/PatPGroAdj}
\begin{comment}
and the proof of Theorem~\ref{thm:MSSBalExists} below yields the conclusion that
\begin{align*}
\lim_{\mRat_{t} \rightarrow \infty} \Ex_{t}[\mRat_{t+1}/\mRat_{t}] & = \PatPGroAdj,
\end{align*}
which implies that if we wish to prevent $\mRat$ from heading to infinity (that is, if we want $\mRat$ to be expected to fall for some large enough value of $m$) we must impose a modified version of the Growth Impatience Condition~\eqref{eq:GICRaw}; we call the `Normalized Growth Impatience Condition' (\GICNrm) the requirement that the Normalized Growth Patience Factor~\eqref{eq:GPFNrm} must be less than 1:\footnote{Under our assumption that $\CRRA>1$, equation~\eqref{eq:GICNrm} is a bit easier to satisfy than the similar condition imposed by Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr}: $\left(\Ex[\pShk^{-\CRRA}]\right)^{1/\CRRA} \PatPGro < 1$ to guarantee that his problem defined a contraction mapping.}
\end{comment}
and a normalized version of the Growth Impatience Condition, {\GICNrm}:
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/GICNrm}
\begin{align}
\PatPGroAdj & < 1 \label{eq:GICNrm},
\end{align}\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\LtxDir\EqDir/GICNrm}
that is stronger than the perfect foresight version~\eqref{eq:GICRaw} because $\PGroAdj < \PGro$.
\begin{comment}
\begin{align}
\PGroAdj & < \PGro \label{eq:PGroAdjLTPGro}.
\end{align}
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{Autarky-Value}{}
\subsubsection{Autarky Value}
Analogously to~\eqref{eq:ValuePFAnalyticalAutarky}, value for a consumer who spent exactly their permanent income every period would reflect the product of the expectation of the (independent) future shocks to permanent income:\hypertarget{uInvEpShkuInv}{}
\begin{align*}
\vLevBF_{t} & = \Ex_{t}\left[\uFunc(\pLevBF_{t}) + \DiscFac \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t}\PGro_{t+1}) + \cdots + \DiscFac^{T-t}\uFunc(\pLevBF_{t}\PGro_{t+1}\ldots\PGro_{T})\right] \\
% & = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(1+ \DiscFac \Ex_{t}[\PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}] + \ldots + \DiscFac^{T-t}\Ex_{t}[\PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}]\ldots\Ex_{t}[\PGro_{T}^{1-\CRRA}]\right) \\
& = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(\frac{1-{(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}\Ex[\pShk^{1-\CRRA}])}^{T-t+1}}{1-\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA} \Ex[\pShk^{1-\CRRA}]}\right),
\end{align*}
suggesting the definition of a utility-compensated equivalent of the permanent shock,\hypertarget{PermGrouAdj}{}
\begin{align}
\uInvEpShkuInv & = {(\Ex[\pShk^{1-\CRRA}])}^{1/(1-\CRRA)} \label{eq:uInvEpShkuInv},
\end{align}
which will satisfy $\uInvEpShkuInv < 1$ for $\CRRA>1$ and nondegenerate $\pShk$.% (and $\uInvEpShkuInv < \InvEpShkInv$ for the reasonable (though not required) case of $\CRRA > 2$);
\hypertarget{DiscAltuAdj}{} Defining
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:PGrouAdj}
\PGrouAdj = \PGro \uInvEpShkuInv,
\end{equation}
$\vLevBF_{t}$ will be positive and finite as $T$ approaches $\infty$ if\hypertarget{FVAC}{}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/FVAC}
\begin{align}
0 < \overbrace{\DiscFac \PGrouAdj^{1-\CRRA} }^{\equiv \DiscAltuAdj} & < 1 \notag
\\ 0 < \DiscFac & < \PGrouAdj^{\CRRA-1} \label{eq:FVAC}
% \\ \DiscFac^{1/\CRRA} & < \PGrouAdj^{1-1/\CRRA}
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
{\input{\LtxDir\EqDir/FVAC}}
We call \eqref{eq:FVAC} the `finite value of autarky condition' because it guarantees that value is finite for a consumer who always consumes their
(now stochastic) permanent income (and we will call $\DiscAltuAdj$ the `Value of Autarky Factor' (or `VAF')).\footnote{In a stationary environment --- that is, with $\PGrouAdj=1$ --- this corresponds to an impatience condition imposed by~\cite{mstIncFluct}; but their remaining conditions do not correspond to those here, because their problem differs and their method of proof differs.} For nondegenerate $\pShk$, this
condition is stronger
(harder to satisfy in the sense of requiring lower $\DiscFac$) than
the perfect foresight version~\eqref{eq:PFFVAC} because $\PGrouAdj <
\PGro$.\footnote{To see this, rewrite~\eqref{eq:FVAC} as
\begin{align*}
\DiscFac \Rfree & < \Rfree \PGrouAdj^{\CRRA-1}
\\ {(\DiscFac \Rfree)}^{1/\CRRA} & < \Rfree^{1/\CRRA} \PGro^{1-1/\CRRA} \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}
\\ \PatPGro & < {(\Rfree/\PGro)}^{1/\CRRA} \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}
\end{align*}
where the last equation is the same as the {\PFFVAC} condition except that the
RHS is multiplied by $\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}$ which is strictly less than 1.}
\hypertarget{Baseline-Numerical-Solution}{}
\subsection{The Baseline Numerical Solution}
Figure~\ref{fig:cFuncsConverge}, familiar from the literature, depicts the successive consumption rules that apply in the last period of life $(\cFunc_{T}(\mRat))$, the second-to-last period, and earlier periods under baseline parameter values listed in Table~\ref{table:Calibration}. (The 45 degree line is $\cFunc_{T}(\mRat) = m$ because in the last period of life it is optimal to spend all remaining resources.)
\hypertarget{Calibration}{}
\input{\TableDir/Parameters}
\hypertarget{Symbols}{}
\input{\TableDir/Calibration}
\renewcommand{\figName}{Convergence-of-the-Consumption-Rules} % Allows generic definition of hypertargets based on title of figure
\renewcommand{\figFile}{cFuncsConverge} % and on filename
\hypertarget{\figFile}{}
\hypertarget{\figName}{}
\input{\FigDir/cFuncsConverge} % Read in the tex to generate the figure
In the figure, the consumption rules appear to converge to a nondegenerate $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)$.
Our next purpose is to show that this appearance is not deceptive. \hypertarget{Concave-Consumption-Function-Characteristics}{}
\subsection{Concave Consumption Function Characteristics}\label{sec:cExists}
A precondition for the main proof is that the maximization problem defines a sequence of continuously differentiable strictly increasing strictly concave\footnote{With one obvious exception: $\usual{\cFunc}_{T}(\mRat)$ is linear (and so only weakly concave).} functions $\{\cFunc_{T},\cFunc_{T-1},\ldots\}$. The straightforward but tedious proof is relegated to Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxcExists}. For present purposes, the most important point is that the income process induces what~\cite{aiyagari:ge} dubbed a `natural borrowing constraint': $\usual{\cFunc}_{t}(\mRat) < m$ for all periods $t < T$ because a consumer who spent all available resources would arrive in period $t+1$ with balances $b_{t+1}$ of zero, and then might earn zero income over the remaining horizon, risking the possibility of a requirement to spend zero, yielding negative infinite utility. To avoid this disaster, the consumer never spends everything.~~\cite{zeldesStochastic} seems to have been the first to argue, based on his numerical results, that the natural borrowing constraint was a quantitatively plausible alternative to `artificial' or `ad hoc' borrowing constraints.\footnote{The same (numerical) point applies for infinite horizon models (calibrated to actual empirical data on household income dynamics); cf.~\cite{carrollBrookings}.}
Strict concavity and continuous differentiability of the consumption function are key elements in many of the arguments below, but are not characteristics of models with `artificial' borrowing constraints -- and we will see below that the analytical convenience of these features is considerable.% --- a point that may appeal to theorists when they realize (cf.\ Section~\ref{sec:LiqConstrAsLimit} below) that the solution to this congenial problem is arbitraily close to the solution to the constrained but less wieldy problem with explicit constraints.
\hypertarget{Bounds-for-the-Consumption-Functions}{}
\subsection{Bounds for the Consumption Functions}\label{subsec:cFuncBounds}
The consumption functions depicted in Figure~\ref{fig:cFuncsConverge} appear to have limiting slopes as $\mRat \downarrow 0$ and as $\mRat \uparrow \infty$. This section confirms that impression and derives those slopes, which will be needed in the contraction mapping proof.\footnote{\cite{benhabibWealth} show that the consumption function becomes linear as wealth approaches infinity in a model with capital income risk and liquidity constraints;~\cite{maTodaRich} show that these results generalize to the limits derived here if capital income is added to the model.}
\newcommand{\NewMaxMinMPC}{\ushort{\MPC}}
Assume (as justified above) that a continuously differentiable concave consumption function exists in period $t+1$, with an origin at $\usual{\cFunc}_{t+1}(0)=0$, a minimal MPC $\NewMaxMinMPC_{t+1}>0$, and maximal MPC $\MaxMPC_{t+1} \leq 1$. (If $t+1 = T$ these will be $\NewMaxMinMPC_{T}=\MaxMPC_{T}=1$; for earlier periods they will exist by recursion.)
Under our imposed assumption that human wealth is finite, the MPC bound as wealth approaches infinity is easy to understand: As the \textit{proportion} of consumption that will be financed out of human wealth approaches zero, the proportional difference between the solution to the model with uncertainty and the perfect foresight model shrinks to zero. \hypertarget{MPCnvrsLower}{} In the course of proving this, Appendix~\ref{sec:MPCLimits} provides a useful recursive expression (used below) for the (inverse of the) limiting MPC:\hypertarget{WRICCond}{}
\begin{align}
\MinMPC_{t}^{-1} & = 1+\MaxMPS \MinMPC_{t+1}^{-1} \label{eq:MinMPCInv}.
\end{align}
\subsubsection{Weak RIC Conditions}{}\label{sec:WRIC}
\hypertarget{MPCnvrsUpper}{}
\hypertarget{WRIC}{}
Appendix equation~\eqref{eq:MaxMPCInvApndx} presents a parallel expression for the limiting maximal MPC as $\mRat_{t} \downarrow 0$:
\begin{align}\hypertarget{WRPF}{}
\MaxMPC_{t}^{-1} & = 1+\MinMPS \MaxMPC_{t+1}^{-1} \label{eq:MaxMPCInv}
\end{align}
where $\left\{\MaxMPC_{T-n}^{-1}\right\} _{n=0}^{\infty}$ is a decreasing % Correction per MNW 2016-01-30
convergent sequence if the `weak return patience factor' $\pZero^{1/\CRRA}\PatR$ satisfies:
\begin{align}
0 \leq & \pZero^{1/\CRRA} \PatR < 1 \label{eq:WRIC},
\end{align}
a condition we dub the `Weak Return Impatience Condition' (\WRIC) because with $\pZero < 1$ it will hold more easily (for a larger set of parameter values) than the \RIC~($\PatR < 1$). The essence of the argument is that as wealth approaches zero, the overriding consideration that limits consumption is the (recursive) fear of the zero-income events. (That is why the probability of the zero income event $\pZero$ appears in the expression.)
\hypertarget{cBounds}{}
We are now in position to observe that the optimal consumption function must satisfy
\begin{align}
\MinMinMPC_{t} \mRat_{t} ~ \leq & ~ \usual{\cFunc}_{t}(\mRat_{t}) \leq ~ \MaxMPC_{t} \mRat_{t} \label{eq:cBounds}
\end{align}
because consumption starts at zero and is continuously differentiable, is strictly concave,\footnote{\cite{ckConcavity}} and always exhibits a slope between $\MinMinMPC_{t}$ and $\MaxMPC_{t}$ (the formal proof is in Appendix~\ref{sec:Tcomplete}).
\begin{comment}
If the \FHWC~does not hold, we make do with a less useful bound on the minimal MPC: It is weakly greater than zero, which follows from the logic in
~\ref{sec:cExists}; hence the `max' in~\eqref{eq:MinMinMPCDef}.
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{Conditions-Under-Which-the-Problem-Defines-a-Contraction-Mapping}{}
\subsection{Conditions Under Which the Problem Defines a Contraction Mapping}\label{subsec:contraction}
%We can now articulate conditions under which the problem defines a contraction mapping.
As mentioned above, standard theorems in the contraction mapping literature following Stokey et.\ al.~\citeyearpar{slpMethods} require utility or marginal utility to be bounded over the space of possible values of $\mRat$, which does not hold here because the possibility (however unlikely) of an unbroken string of zero-income events through the end of the horizon means that utility (and marginal utility) are unbounded as $\mRat \downarrow 0$. Although a recent literature examines the existence and uniqueness of solutions to Bellman equations in the presence of `unbounded returns' (see, e.g.,~\cite{mnUnique}), the techniques in that literature cannot be used to solve the problem here because the required conditions are violated by a problem that incorporates permanent shocks.\footnote{See~\cite{yaoNote} for a detailed discussion of the reasons the existing literature up through~\cite{mnUnique} cannot handle the problem described here.}
Fortunately, Boyd~\citeyearpar{jboydWeighted} provided a weighted contraction mapping theorem that~\cite{asHomogeneous} showed could be used to address the homogeneous case (of which CRRA is an example) in a deterministic framework; later,~\cite{duranDiscounting} showed how to extend the~\cite{jboydWeighted} approach to the stochastic case.
\begin{defn}
Consider any function $\bullet\in \mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ where $\mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ is the space of continuous functions from $\mathscr{A}$ to $%
\mathscr{B}$. Suppose $\phiFunc \in \mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ with $%
\mathscr{B}\subseteq\mathbb{R}$ and $\phiFunc >0$. Then $\bullet$ is $\phiFunc$-bounded if the $\phiFunc$-norm of $\bullet$,
\begin{equation}
\Vert \bullet\Vert _{\phiFunc }=\sup_{\mRat}\left[ \frac{|\bullet(\mRat)|}{\phiFunc (\mRat)}\right] ,
\label{eq:phinorm}
\end{equation}%
is finite.
\end{defn}
For $\mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) $ defined as the set of functions in $\mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ that are $\phiFunc$-bounded; $\wFunc$, $\xFunc$, $\yFunc$, and $\zFunc$ as examples of $\phiFunc$-bounded functions; and using {$\mathbf{0}(\mRat)=0$} to indicate the function that returns zero for any argument, Boyd~\citeyearpar{jboydWeighted} proves the following.
\textbf{Boyd's Weighted Contraction Mapping Theorem.} \textit{Let $\BoydT:\mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right)
\rightarrow \mathcal{C}\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) $ such
that}\footnote{We will usually denote the function that results from the mapping as, e.g., $\{\BoydT\wFunc\}$.}\textsuperscript{,}\footnote{To non-theorists, this notation may be slightly confusing; the inequality relations in (1) and (3) are taken to mean `for any specific element $\bullet$ in the domain of the functions in question' so that, e.g., $\xFunc \leq \yFunc$ is short for $\xFunc(\bullet) \leq \yFunc(\bullet)~\forall~\bullet\in \mathscr{A}$. In this notation, $\zeta \Shrinker \phiFunc$ in (3) is a \textit{function} which can be applied to any argument $\bullet$ (because $\phiFunc$ is a function).} \nopagebreak
\begin{align*}
\mbox{(1)} &\BoydT%
\mbox{ \textit{is non-decreasing, i.e.\ ${\xFunc} \leq {\yFunc}\Rightarrow
\{\BoydT{\xFunc}\} \leq \{\BoydT{\yFunc}\}$}} \nonumber \\
\mbox{(2)} & \{\BoydT\mathbf{0}\}\in ~ \mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) \notag \\
\mbox{(3)}
& \mbox{\textit{There exists some real $0 < \Shrinker < 1$ such that}} \\
& \{\BoydT({\wFunc} +\zeta\phiFunc )\} \leq \{\BoydT{\wFunc}\} +\zeta\Shrinker \phiFunc
\mbox{ \textit{~~holds for all real $\zeta > 0$ } } .
\end{align*}
\textit{Then $\BoydT$ defines a contraction with a unique fixed point.}
For our problem, take $\mathscr{A}$ as $\mathbb{R}_{>0}$ and $\mathscr{B}$
as $\mathbb{R}$, and define
\begin{align*}
\{\EEndMap \zFunc\}(a_{t}) & = \Ex_{t}\left[\PGro^{1-\CRRA}_{t+1} \zFunc(a_{t} \Rnorm_{t+1} + \tShkAll_{t+1})\right].
\end{align*}
Using this, we introduce the mapping \textit{$\TMap:\mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) \rightarrow \mathcal{C}\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) $}.\footnote{Note that the existence of the maximum is assured by the continuity of $\{\EEndMap \zFunc\}(a_{t})$ (it is continuous because it is the sum of continuous $\phiFunc$-bounded functions $\zFunc$) and the compactness of $[\MinMinMPC \mRat_{t}, \MaxMPC \mRat_{t}]$.}
\hypertarget{Contraction-Conditions}{}
We can show that our operator $\TMap$ satisfies the conditions that Boyd requires of his operator $\BoydT$, if we impose two restrictions on parameter values. The first is the \WRIC~necessary for convergence of the maximal MPC, equation~\eqref{eq:WRIC} above. More serious is the Finite Value of Autarky condition, equation~\eqref{eq:FVAC}. (We discuss the interpretation of these restrictions in detail in Section~\ref{sec:discussConvergence} below.) Imposing these restrictions, we are now in position to state the central theorem of the paper.
\hypertarget{MainTheorem}{}
\setcounter{theorem}{0}
\begin{theorem}\label{thm:contmap}
$\TMap$ is a contraction mapping if the restrictions on parameter values~\eqref{eq:WRIC} and~\eqref{eq:FVAC} are true (that is, if the weak return impatience condition and the finite value of autarky condition hold).
\end{theorem}
Intuitively, Boyd's theorem shows that if you can find a $\phiFunc$ that is everywhere finite but goes to infinity `as fast or faster' than the function you are normalizing with $\phiFunc$, the normalized problem defines a contraction mapping. The intuition for the {\FVAC} condition is that, with an infinite horizon, with any initial amount of bank balances $\bRat_{0}$, in the limit your value can always be made greater than you would get by consuming exactly the sustainable amount (say, by consuming $(\rfree/\Rfree)\bRat_{0}-\epsilon$ for some small $\epsilon>0$).
The cumbersome details of the proof are relegated to Appendix~\ref{sec:Tcomplete}. Given that the value function converges, Appendix~\ref{subsec:cConverges} shows that the consumption functions converge.\footnote{MST's proof is for convergence of the consumption policy function directly, rather than of the value function, which is why their conditions are on $\uFunc^{\prime}$, which governs behavior.}
\hypertarget{The-Liquidity-Constrained-Solution-as-a-Limit}{}
\subsection{The Liquidity Constrained Solution as a Limit}\label{sec:deatonIsLimit}
This section explains why a related problem commonly considered in the literature (e.g., by Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr}), with a liquidity constraint and a positive minimum value of income, is the limit of the problem considered here as the probability $\pZero$ of the zero-income event approaches zero.
The `related' problem makes two changes to the problem defined above:
\begin{enumerate}
\item An `artificial' liquidity constraint is imposed: $\aRat_{t}\geq 0$
\item The probability of zero-income events is zero: $\pZero=0$
\end{enumerate}
The essence of the argument is simple. Imposing the artificial constraint without changing $\pZero$ would not change behavior at all: The possibility of earning zero income over the remaining horizon already prevents the consumer from ending the period with zero assets. So, for precautionary reasons, the consumer will save something.
But the \textit{extent} to which the consumer feels the need to make this precautionary provision depends on the \textit{probability} that it will turn out to matter. As $\pZero \downarrow 0$, that probability becomes arbitrarily small, so the \textit{amount} of precautionary saving induced by the zero-income events approaches zero as $\pZero \downarrow 0$. But ``zero'' is the amount of precautionary saving that would be induced by a zero-probability event for the impatient liquidity constrained consumer.
Another way to understand this is just to think of the liquidity
constraint reflecting a component of the utility
function that is zero whenever the consumer ends the period with
(strictly) positive assets, but negative infinity if the consumer
ends the period with (weakly) negative assets.
See Appendix~\ref{sec:LiqConstrAsLimit} for the formal proof justifying the
foregoing intuitive discussion.\footnote{It seems likely that a similar argument
would apply even in the context of a model like that of MST, perhaps with some weak
restrictions on returns.}
The conditions required for convergence and nondegeneracy are thus strikingly similar between the liquidity constrained perfect foresight model and the model with uncertainty but no explicit constraints: The liquidity constrained perfect foresight model is just the limiting case of the model with uncertainty as the degree of all three kinds of uncertainty (zero-income events, other transitory shocks, and permanent shocks) approaches zero.
% \hypertarget{Restrained-Consumer}{}
% In the remainder of the paper, in order to avoid a confusion that is common in discussions of models of this type, we will refer to consumers who are solving a problem in which constraints exist, but are not necessarily binding at the moment under consideration, as `restrained' consumers.
\hypertarget{Discussion-of-Parametric-Restrictions}{}
\subsection{Discussion of Parametric Restrictions}\label{sec:discussConvergence}
The full relationship among conditions is represented in Figure~\ref{fig:Inequalities}. Though the diagram looks complex, it is merely a modified version of the earlier diagram (Figure~\ref{fig:RelatePFGICFHWCRICPFFVAC}) with further (mostly intermediate) inequalities inserted. (Arrows with a ``because'' now label relations that always hold under the model's assumptions.)\footnote{Again, readers unfamiliar with such diagrams should see Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxConditionDiagrams} for a more detailed exposition.}
\renewcommand{\figName}{Inequalities} % Allows generic definition of hypertargets based on title of figure
\renewcommand{\figFile}{\figName} % and on filename
\hypertarget{\figFile}{}
%\hypertarget{\figName}{}
\input{\FigDir/\figName} % Read in the tex to generate the figure
\subsubsection{The \WRIC}\label{subsubsec:WRICdiscuss}
The `weakness' of the additional condition sufficient for contraction beyond the {\FVAC}, the
\WRIC, can be seen by asking `under what circumstances
would the \FVAC~hold but the \WRIC~fail?'
Algebraically, the requirement is
\begin{align}
\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-\CRRA} & < ~ 1 ~ < {(\pZero \DiscFac)}^{1/\CRRA}/\Rfree^{1-1/\CRRA}. \label{eq:WRICandFVAC}
\end{align}
If we require $\Rfree \geq 1$, the {\WRIC}~is redundant because now $\DiscFac <1<\Rfree^{\CRRA-1}$, so that (with $\CRRA > 1$ and $\DiscFac<1$) the \RIC~(and \WRIC) must hold. But neither theory nor evidence demand that $\Rfree \geq
1$. We can therefore approach the question of the \WRIC's relevance by asking just how low $\Rfree$ must be for the condition to be relevant.
Suppose for illustration that $\CRRA=2$, $\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-\CRRA}=1.01$,
$\PGro^{1-\CRRA}=1.01^{-1}$ and $\pZero = 0.10$. In that case~\eqref{eq:WRICandFVAC} reduces to
\begin{align*}
\DiscFac & < 1 < {(0.1 \DiscFac/\Rfree)}^{1/2}
\end{align*}
but since $\DiscFac < 1$ by assumption, the binding requirement is that
\begin{align*}
\Rfree & < \DiscFac/10 \notag
\end{align*}
so that for example if $\DiscFac=0.96$ we would need $\Rfree < 0.096$
(that is, a perpetual riskfree rate of return of worse than -90
percent a year) in order for the \WRIC~to bind. %The relevance of the \WRIC~is indeed ``Weak.''
Perhaps the best way of thinking about this is to note that the space of parameter values for which the \WRIC~is relevant shrinks out of existence as $\pZero \rightarrow 0$, which Section~\ref{sec:deatonIsLimit} showed was the precise limiting condition under which behavior becomes arbitrarily close to the liquidity constrained solution (in the absence of other risks). On the other hand, when $\pZero = 1$, the consumer has no noncapital income (so that the \FHWC~holds) and with $\pZero=1$ the \WRIC~is identical to the RIC;\@ but the \RIC~is the only condition required for a solution to exist for a perfect foresight consumer with no noncapital income. Thus the WRIC~forms a sort of `bridge' between the liquidity constrained and the unconstrained problems as $\pZero$ moves from 0 to 1.
\hypertarget{IntuitionRIC}{}
\subsubsection{When the \RIC~Fails}\label{subsubsec:WhenTheRICFails}
In the perfect foresight problem (Section~\ref{subsec:PFUncon}), the \RIC~was necessary for existence of a nondegenerate solution. It is surprising, therefore, that in the presence of uncertainty, the much weaker {\WRIC} is sufficient for nondegeneracy (assuming that the {\FVAC} holds).
\begin{comment}
But if the \RIC~does hold, some useful results can be derived. Arguably
the most fundamental are that the limiting values
for the minimal and maximal marginal propensities to consume implicit in
~\eqref{eq:MaxMPCInv} and~\eqref{eq:MinMPCInv} are positive and finite.
\end{comment}
We can directly derive the features the problem must
exhibit (given the \FVAC) under \cncl{\RIC} (that is, $\Rfree < {(\Rfree \DiscFac)}^{1/\CRRA})$:
\begin{align}
\Rfree & < \overbrace{{(\Rfree \DiscFac)}^{1/\CRRA} ~ < ~ {(\Rfree {(\PGro \uInvEpShkuInv)}^{\CRRA-1})}^{1/\CRRA}}^{\text{implied by \FVAC}} \notag
\\ \Rfree & < {(\Rfree/\PGro)}^{1/\CRRA}\PGro \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA} \notag
\\ \Rfree/\PGro & < {(\Rfree/\PGro)}^{1/\CRRA}\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA} \notag
\\ \Rfree/\PGro & < \uInvEpShkuInv \label{eq:RICimplies}
\end{align}
but since $\uInvEpShkuInv < 1$ (cf.\ the argument below~\eqref{eq:uInvEpShkuInv}), this requires $\Rfree/\PGro < 1$; so, given the \FVAC, the \RIC~can fail only if human wealth is unbounded. As an illustration of the usefulness of our diagrams, note that this algebraically complicated conclusion could be easily reached diagrammatically in figure~\ref{fig:Inequalities} by starting at the $\Rfree$ node and imposing $\cncl{\RIC}$, reversing the {\RIC} arrow and then traversing the diagram along any clockwise path to the {\PFVAF} node at which point we realize that we \textit{cannot} impose the {\FHWC} because that would let us conclude $\Rfree > \Rfree$.
As in the perfect foresight constrained problem, unbounded limiting human wealth (\cncl{\FHWC}) here does not lead to a degenerate limiting consumption function (finite human wealth is not a condition required for the convergence theorem). But, from equation~\eqref{eq:MinMPCInv} and the discussion surrounding it, an implication of \cncl{\RIC} is that $\lim_{m \uparrow \infty} \usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat) = 0$. Thus, interestingly, in the special $\{\cncl{\RIC},\cncl{\FHWC}\}$ case (unavailable in the perfect foresight model) the presence of uncertainty both permits unlimited human wealth (in the $n\uparrow\infty$ limit) and at the same time prevents unlimited human wealth from resulting in (limiting) infinite consumption at any finite $\mRat$. Intutively, in the presence of uncertainty, pathological patience (which in the perfect foresight model results in a limiting consumption function of $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)=0$ for finite $\mRat$) plus unbounded human wealth (which the perfect foresight model prohibits because it leads to a limiting consumption function $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\infty$ for any finite $\mRat$) combine to yield a unique finite limiting (as $n \uparrow \infty$) level of consumption and MPC for any finite value of $\mRat$. Note the close parallel to the conclusion in the perfect foresight liquidity constrained model in the \{\GICRaw,\cncl{\RIC}\} case. There, too, the tension between infinite human wealth and pathological patience was resolved with a nondegenerate consumption function whose limiting MPC was zero.\footnote{\cite{maTodaRich} derive conditions under which the limiting MPC is zero in an even more general case where there is also capital income risk.}
\hypertarget{When-the-RIC-Holds}{}
\subsubsection{When the {\RIC} Holds}\label{subsubsec:WhenTheGICNrmFails}\label{subsubsec:WhenTheRICHolds}
\indent \textbf{\FHWC}. If the {\RIC} and {\FHWC} both hold, a perfect foresight solution exists (see~\ref{subsec:PFUncon} above). As $\mRat \uparrow \infty$ the limiting consumption function and value function become arbitrarily close to those in the perfect foresight model, because human wealth pays for a vanishingly small portion of spending. This will be the main case analyzed in detail below.
\begin{comment}
\begin{align}
\Rfree^{1/\CRRA}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA} & < \Pat < \Rfree^{1/\CRRA}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}
\\ \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}(\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA-1} & < \PatR < 1 < (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA-1}
\\ \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}\Rfree^{1/\CRRA-1}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA} & < \Rfree^{1/\CRRA}\DiscFac^{1/\CRRA}/\Rfree < 1 < \Rfree^{1/\CRRA-1}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}
\\ \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}\Rfree^{-1}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA} & < \DiscFac^{1/\CRRA}/\Rfree < \Rfree^{-1/\CRRA} < \Rfree^{-1}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}
\\ \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA} & < \DiscFac^{1/\CRRA} < \Rfree^{1-1/\CRRA} < \PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}
\\ \uInvEpShkuInv^{(\CRRA-1)/\CRRA}\PGro^{(\CRRA-1)/\CRRA} & < \DiscFac^{1/\CRRA} < \Rfree^{(\CRRA-1)/\CRRA} < \PGro^{(\CRRA-1)/\CRRA}
\\ \uInvEpShkuInv^{\CRRA-1} & < \DiscFac/\PGro < 1
\\ \PGro \uInvEpShkuInv^{\CRRA-1} & < \DiscFac < \PGro
\end{align}
\end{comment}
\noindent \textbf{\cncl{\FHWC}}. The more exotic case is where {\FHWC} does not hold; in the perfect foresight model, \{{\RIC},\cncl{\FHWC}\} is the degenerate case with limiting $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\infty$. Here, since the {\FVAC} implies that the {\PFFVAC} holds (traverse Figure~\ref{fig:Inequalities} clockwise from $\Pat$ by imposing {\FVAC} and continue to the {\PFVAF} node): Reversing the arrow connecting the $\Rfree$ and {\PFVAF} nodes implies that under $\cncl{\FHWC}$:
\begin{align*}
& \overbrace{\Pat < {(\Rfree/\PGro)}^{1/\CRRA}\PGro}^{\PFFVAC}
\\ & \Pat < \PGro
\end{align*}
where the transition from the first to the second lines is justified because $\cncl{\FHWC} \Rightarrow {(\Rfree/\PGro)}^{1/\CRRA}<1$. So, \{\RIC, \cncl{\FHWC}\} implies the {\GICRaw} holds. However, we are not entitled to conclude that the {\GICNrm} holds: $\Pat < \PGro$ does not imply $\Pat < \InvEpShkInv \PGro$ where $\InvEpShkInv<1$. %See further discussion of this illuminating case in section~\ref{subsubsec:FVACnotGIC}.
\begin{comment}
Finally, we are entitled to conclude that $\lim_{\mRat \uparrow \infty} \MPC(\mRat) = \MinMPC$ because, for any fixed value of $\pZero > 0$, and any fixed horizon $n$ it must be true that:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $\usual{\cFunc}_{T-n}(\mRat) < \bar{\cFunc}_{T-n}$ for the reasons described in the section on the liquidity constrained model above
\item As $\mRat \uparrow \infty$ the \textit{amount} by which $\bar{\cFunc}$ exceeds $\usual{\cFunc}$ approaches zero.
\end{enumerate}
%This result introduces the discussion of the last interesting parametric question, which is implications the alternative versions of the Growth Impatience Condition (continuing to assume the {\FVAC} and {\WRIC} conditions required for nondegeneracy).
\end{comment}
We have now established the principal points of comparison between the perfect foresight solutions and the solutions under uncertainty; these are codified in the remaining parts of Tables~\ref{table:Comparison} and~\ref{table:Required}.
\hypertarget{Factors-Defined-And-Compared}{}
\input{\TableDir/Comparison}
\hypertarget{Sufficient-Conditions}{}
\hypertarget{Sufficient-Conditions-For-Nondegenerate-Solution}{}
\input{\TableDir/Required}
\hypertarget{AnalysisoftheConvergedConsumptionFunction}{}
\section{Analysis of the Converged Consumption Function}\label{sec:convergedcfunc}
Figures~\ref{fig:cGroTargetFig}-\ref{fig:cFuncBounds} capture the main properties of the converged consumption rule when the \RIC, \GICNrm, and \FHWC~all hold.\footnote{These figures reflect the converged rule corresponding to the parameter values indicated in Table~\ref{table:Calibration}.}
Figure~\ref{fig:cGroTargetFig} shows the expected growth factors for consumption, the level of market resources, and the market resources ratio, $\Ex_{t}[\cLevBF_{t+1}/\cLevBF_{t}]$ and $\Ex_{t}[\mLevBF_{t+1}/\mLevBF_{t}]$, and $\Ex_{t}[\mRat_{t+1}/\mRat_{t}]$, for a consumer behaving according to the converged consumption rule, while Figures~\ref{fig:mpclimits}---\ref{fig:cFuncBounds} illustrate theoretical bounds for the consumption function and the MPC.
Three points are worth highlighting. % features of behavior are captured, or suggested, by the figures.
First, as $\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty$ the expected consumption growth factor goes to ${\Pat}$, indicated by the lower bound in Figure~\ref{fig:cGroTargetFig}, and the marginal propensity to consume approaches $\MinMPC=(1-\PatR)$ (see Figure~\ref{fig:mpclimits}) --- the same as the perfect foresight MPC.\@ Second, as $\mRat_{t}$ approaches zero the consumption growth factor approaches $\infty$ (Figure~\ref{fig:cGroTargetFig}) and the MPC approaches $\MaxMPC=(1-\pZero^{1/\CRRA}\PatR)$ (Figure~\ref{fig:mpclimits}). Third, there is a value of the market resources ratio $\mRat_{t} = \mStE$ at which the expected growth rate of the level of market resources $\mLevBF$ matches the expected growth rate of permanent income $\PGro$, and a different (larger) target ratio $\mTrg$ where $\Ex[\mRat_{t+1}/\mRat_{t}]=1$ and the expected growth rate of consumption is lower than $\PGro$. Thus, at the individual level, this model does not have a single $\mRat$ at which $\pLevBF,~\mLevBF,~$ and $\cLevBF$ all grow at the same rate.\footnote{A final proposition suggested by Figure~\ref{fig:cGroTargetFig} is that the expected consumption growth factor is declining in the level of the cash-on-hand ratio $\mRat_{t}$. This turns out to be true in the absence of permanent shocks, but in extreme cases it can be false if permanent shocks are present; see Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxCGrowthDeclines}.}
\begin{comment}
Third (Figure~\ref{fig:cGroTargetFig}), there are two special values of $\mRat$, which we will call the `individual balanced growth' point $\mStE$ because it is the point where expected consumption growth and expected permanent income growth are balanced, and the `individual target' $\mTrg$ such that if $\mRat_t = \mTrg$ then $\Ex_t [{\mRat}_{t+1}] = \mRat_t$. %As indicated by the arrows of motion on the $\Ex_{t}[\cLevBF_{t+1}/\cLevBF_{t}]$ curve, the model's dynamics are `stable' around this target in the sense that if $\mRat_{t} < \mTrg$ then $\mRat$ will rise (in expectation), while if $\mRat_{t} > \mTrg$, it will fall (in expectation).Fourth (Figure~\ref{fig:cGroTargetFig}), at the market resources target $\mTrg$, the expected rate of growth of consumption is slightly less than the expected growth rate
of permanent noncapital income. (The individual consumer does not expect `balanced growth' at $\mTrg$).
The final proposition suggested by Figure~\ref{fig:cGroTargetFig} is that the expected consumption growth factor is declining in the level of the cash-on-hand ratio $\mRat_{t}$. This turns out to be true in the absence of permanent shocks, but in extreme cases it can be false if permanent shocks are present.\footnote{Throughout the remaining analysis I make a final assumption that is not strictly justified by the foregoing. We have seen that the finite-horizon consumption functions $\usual{\cFunc}_{T-n}(\mRat)$ are twice continuously differentiable and strictly concave, and that they converge to a continuous function $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)$. It does not strictly follow that the limiting function $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)$ is twice continuously differentiable, but I will assume that it is.}
\end{comment}
\renewcommand{\figFile}{cGroTargetFig}
\hypertarget{\figFile}{}
\input{\FigDir/cGroTargetFig}
\hypertarget{LimitsAsmtToInfty}{}
\subsection{Limits as \texorpdfstring{$\mRat$}{m} approaches Infinity}\label{subsec:LimitsAsmtToInfty}
Define
\begin{align*}
\ushort{\cFunc}(\mRat) & = \MinMPC \mRat
\end{align*}
which is the solution to an infinite-horizon problem with no noncapital income ($\tShkAll_{t+n} = 0~\forall~n\geq1$); clearly $\ushort{\cFunc}(\mRat) < \usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)$, since allowing the possibility of future noncapital income cannot reduce current consumption. Our imposition of the {\RIC} guarantees that $\MinMPC > 0$, so this solution satisfies our definition of nondegeneracy, and because this solution is always available it defines a lower bound on both the consumption and value functions.%\footnote{We will assume the \RIC~holds here and subsequently so that $\MinMPC > 0$; the situation is a bit more complex when the \RIC~does not hold. In that case the bound on consumption is given by the spending that would be undertaken by a consumer who faced binding liquidity constraints.}
Assuming the \FHWC~holds, the infinite horizon perfect foresight solution~\eqref{eq:cFuncPFUnc} constitutes an upper bound on consumption in the presence of uncertainty, since the introduction of uncertainty strictly decreases the level of consumption at any $\mRat$ (\cite{ckConcavity}). Thus, we can write
\begin{align}
\ushort{\cFunc}(\mRat) < & \usual{\cFunc}(\mRat) < \bar{\cFunc}(\mRat) \label{eq:lowerltupper} \\
1 < & \usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)/\ushort{\cFunc}(\mRat) < \bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)/\ushort{\cFunc}(\mRat). \nonumber
\end{align}
But
\begin{align*} \label{eq:limitlowerupper}
\lim_{m \uparrow \infty} \bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)/\ushort{\cFunc}(\mRat)
& = \lim_{m \uparrow \infty} (\mRat -1+ \hRat)/\mRat \\
& = 1,
\end{align*}
so as $\mRat \uparrow \infty, \usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)/\ushort{\cFunc}(\mRat)
\rightarrow 1$, and the continuous differentiability and strict
concavity of $\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)$ therefore implies
\begin{equation*} \label{eq:limxtoinftycp}
\lim_{m \uparrow \infty} \usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat) =
\ushort{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat) = \bar{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat) = \MinMPC
\end{equation*}
because any other fixed limit would eventually lead to a level of
consumption either exceeding $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)$ or lower than
$\ushort{\cFunc}(\mRat)$.
Figure~\ref{fig:mpclimits} confirms these limits visually. The top
plot shows the converged consumption function along with its upper and lower bounds,
while the lower plot shows the marginal propensity to consume.
\renewcommand{\figFile}{mpclimits}
\hypertarget{\figFile}{}
\input{\FigDir/MPCLimits}
\renewcommand{\figFile}{cFuncBounds}
\hypertarget{\figFile}{}
\input{\FigDir/cFuncBounds}
Next we establish the limit of the expected consumption growth factor
as $\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty$:
\begin{align*}
\lim_{\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty} \Ex_{t}[
\cLevBF_{t+1}/\cLevBF_{t}] & = \lim_{\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty} \Ex_{t}[
{\PGro}_{t+1} {\cRat}_{t+1}/c_{t}].
\end{align*}
But
\begin{align*}
\Ex_{t}[{\PGro}_{t+1} {\ushort{\cRat}}_{t+1}/\bar{\cRat_{t}}] \leq \Ex_{t}[{\PGro}_{t+1} {\cRat}_{t+1}/\cRat_{t}] \leq \Ex_{t}[{\PGro}_{t+1} {\bar{\cRat}}_{t+1}/\ushort{\cRat}_{t}]
\end{align*}
and
\begin{equation*} \label{eq:xttoinfty}
\lim_{\mRat_t \uparrow \infty} \PGro_{t+1}\ushort{\cFunc}(\mRat_{t+1})/\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat_t) =
\lim_{\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty} \PGro_{t+1}\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat_{t+1})/\ushort{\cFunc}(\mRat_t) =
\lim_{\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty}\PGro_{t+1} \mRat_{t+1}/\mRat_t,
\end{equation*}
while (for convenience defining $\aFunc(\mRat_{t})=\mRat_{t}-\usual{\cFunc}(\mRat_{t})$), \hypertarget{xtp1toinfty}{}
\begin{align} \label{eq:xtp1toinfty}
\lim_{\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty} \PGro_{t+1} \mRat_{t+1}/\mRat_t & = \lim_{\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty}
\left(\frac{\Rfree \aFunc(\mRat_t)+{\PGro}_{t+1}\tShkAll_{t+1}}{\mRat_t}\right)
\\ & = {(\Rfree \DiscFac)}^{1/\CRRA} = \Pat \notag
\end{align}
because $\lim_{\mRat_{t}\uparrow \infty} \aFunc^{\prime}(\mRat)=\PatR$\footnote{This is because $\lim_{\mRat_{t}\uparrow \infty} \aFunc(\mRat_{t})/\mRat_{t}=1-\lim_{\mRat_{t}\uparrow \infty} \usual{\cFunc}(\mRat_{t})/\mRat_{t}=1-\lim_{\mRat_{t}\uparrow \infty}\usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat_{t})=\PatR$.} and
$\PGro_{t+1}\tShkAll_{t+1}/\mRat_{t} \leq (\PGro \bar{\pShk} \bar{\tShkEmp}/\pNotZero )/\mRat_{t}$ which
goes to zero as $\mRat_{t}$ goes to infinity.
Hence we have
\begin{equation*}
{\Pat} \leq \lim_{\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty} \Ex_{t}[\cLevBF_{t+1}/\cLevBF_{t}] \leq {\Pat}
\end{equation*}
so as cash goes to infinity, consumption growth approaches its
value $\Pat$ in the perfect foresight model.
% This argument applies equally well to the problem of the restrained consumer, because as $\mRat$ approaches infinity the constraint becomes irrelevant (assuming the \FHWC~holds).
\begin{comment}
Of course, the constraint never becomes irrelevant if human wealth is
infinite. We ruled out infinite human wealth at the beginning of this
section by assuming $\Rfree> \PGro$. If this finite human wealth
condition does not hold, it is possible to show that for any finite
horizon consumer the marginal propensity to consume approaches the
finite-horizon perfect foresight MPC as wealth approaches infinity.
However, as the horizon gets longer, the perfect foresight MPC
approaches zero. It can be shown therefore that the limiting MPC for
the converged consumption function approaches (but never reaches)
zero. (This is why we chose $\MinMinMPC=0$ if the \FHWC~fails
in the proofs above.)
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{LimitsAsmtToZero}{}
\subsection{Limits as \texorpdfstring{$\mRat$}{m} Approaches Zero}\label{subsec:LimitsAsmtToZero}
%\label{subsec:LimitsAsmtToZero} Now consider the limits of behavior as $\mRat_{t}$ gets arbitrarily small.
Equation~\eqref{eq:MaxMPCInv} shows that the limiting value of
$\MaxMPC$ is
\begin{align*}
\MaxMPC & = 1-{\Rfree}^{-1}{(\pZero \Rfree\DiscFac)}^{1/\CRRA}.
\end{align*}
Defining $\eFunc(\mRat)=\cFunc(\mRat)/\mRat$ as before we have
\begin{align*}
\lim_{m \downarrow 0} \eFunc(\mRat) & = (1-\pZero^{1/\CRRA}\PatR) = \MaxMPC .
\end{align*}
Now using the continuous differentiability of the consumption function
along with L'H\^opital's rule, we have
\begin{comment}
\begin{align*}
\eFunc^{\prime}(\mRat) & = \mRat^{-1} \usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat) - \mRat^{-2} \usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)
\\ \mRat \eFunc^{\prime}(\mRat) & = \usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat) - \usual{\cFunc}(\mRat)/\mRat
\\ \usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat) & = \eFunc(\mRat)+ \mRat \eFunc^{\prime}(\mRat)
\end{align*}
and since $0<\eFunc(\mRat)<1$ we have
\end{comment}
\begin{align*}
\lim_{m \downarrow 0} \usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat) & = \lim_{m \downarrow 0}
\eFunc(\mRat) = \MaxMPC.
\end{align*}
Figure~\ref{fig:mpclimits} confirms that the numerical solution obtains this limit for the MPC as $\mRat$ approaches zero.
For consumption growth, as $\mRat \downarrow 0$ we have
\begin{align*}
\lim_{\mRat_{t} \downarrow 0} \Ex_{t}\left[\left(\frac{\cFunc({\mRat}_{t+1})}{\cFunc(\mRat_t)}\right){\PGro}_{t+1}\right]
& > \lim_{\mRat_{t} \downarrow 0} \Ex_{t}\left[\left(\frac{\ushort{\cFunc}({\mathcal{\mathcal{R}}}_{t+1}\aFunc(\mRat_{t})+{%
\tShkAll}_{t+1})}{\MaxMPC \mRat_{t}}\right){\PGro}_{t+1}\right] \notag \\
& = \pZero \lim_{\mRat_{t} \downarrow 0} \Ex_{t}\left[\left(\frac{\ushort{\cFunc}({\mathcal{\mathcal{R}}}_{t+1}\aFunc(\mRat_{t}))}{\MaxMPC \mRat_{t}}\right){\PGro}_{t+1}\right] \\
& ~~~~~~ + \pNotZero \lim_{\mRat_{t} \downarrow 0} \Ex_{t}\left[\left(\frac{\ushort{\cFunc}({\mathcal{\mathcal{R}}}_{t+1}\aFunc(\mRat_{t})+
\tShkEmp_{t+1}/\pNotZero)}{\MaxMPC \mRat_{t}}\right){\PGro}_{t+1}\right] \\\notag
& > \pNotZero \lim_{\mRat_{t} \downarrow 0} \Ex_{t}\left[\left(\frac{\ushort{\cFunc}(
\tShkEmp_{t+1}/\pNotZero)}{\MaxMPC \mRat_{t}}\right){\PGro}_{t+1}\right] \\
& = \infty \nonumber
\end{align*}
where the second-to-last line follows because $\lim_{\mRat_{t} \downarrow 0} \Ex_{t}\left[\left(\frac{\ushort{\cFunc}({\mathcal{\mathcal{R}}}_{t+1}\aFunc(\mRat_{t}))}{\MaxMPC \mRat_{t}}\right){\PGro}_{t+1}\right]$ is positive, and the last line follows because the minimum possible realization of $\tShkEmp_{t+1}$ is $\ushort{\tShkEmp}>0$ so the minimum possible value of expected next-period consumption is positive.\footnote{None of the arguments in either of the two prior sections depended on the assumption that the consumption functions had converged. With more cumbersome notation, each derivation could have been replaced by the corresponding finite-horizon versions. This strongly suggests that it should be possible to extend the circumstances under which the problem can be shown to define a contraction mapping to the union of the parameter values under which \{\RIC,\FHWC\} hold and \{\FVAC,\WRIC\} hold. That extension is not necessary for our purposes here, so we leave it for future work.}
\hypertarget{onetarget}{}
\hypertarget{Unique-Stable-Points}{}
\subsection{Unique `Stable' Points}\label{subsec:onetarget}\hypertarget{TheoremTarget}{}
Two theorems, whose substance is described here and whose details are in an appendix, articulate alternative (but closely related) stability criteria for the model.
\subsubsection{`Individual Target Wealth'}\label{subsubsec:mTarget}
One definition of a `stable' point is what we will call a `target' value $\mTrg$ such that if $\mRat_{t}=\mTrg$, then $\Ex_{t}[\mRat_{t+1}]=\mRat_{t}$. Existence of such a target turns out to require the {\GICNrm} condition.
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/TheoremMTargetIsStable}
\begin{theorem}\label{thm:target}
For the nondegenerate solution to the problem defined in Section~\ref{subsec:Setup} when {\FVAC}, {\WRIC}, and {\GICNrm} all hold, there exists a unique cash-on-hand-to-permanent-income ratio $\mTrg>0$ such that
\begin{equation}
\Ex_t [{\mRat}_{t+1}/\mRat_t] = 1 \mbox{~if~} \mRat_t = \mTrg.
\label{eq:mTarget}
\end{equation}
Moreover, $\mTrg$ is a point of `wealth stability' in the sense that
\begin{align}\label{eq:stability}
\forall {\mRat}_t\in(0,\mTrg), \,\,& \Ex_t [{\mRat}_{t+1}] > {\mRat}_t \\
\forall {\mRat}_t\in(\mTrg,\infty), \,\,& \Ex_t [{\mRat}_{t+1}] < {\mRat}_t. \notag
\end{align}
\end{theorem}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\LtxDir\EqDir/TheoremMTargetIsStable}
\hypertarget{mTargImplicit}{}
Since $\mRat_{t+1}=(\mRat_{t}-\cFunc(\mRat_{t}))\Rnorm_{t+1}+\tShk_{t+1}$, the implicit equation for $\mTrg$ is
\begin{align}
\Ex_{t}[(\mTrg-\cFunc(\mTrg))\Rnorm_{t+1}+\tShk_{t+1}] & = \mTrg \label{eq:mTargImplicit}
\\ (\mTrg-\cFunc(\mTrg))\underbrace{\Rnorm\Ex_{t}[\pShk^{-1}]}_{\equiv \bar{\Rnorm}}+1 & = \mTrg \notag
\end{align}
\begin{comment}
The full proof is in Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxMTargetIsStable}, but the key points can be made informally here. Existence of such a point is guaranteed by
\begin{enumerate}
\item Existence, continuity, and monotonicity of $\Ex_t [{\mRat}_{t+1}-\mRat_t]$
\item $\lim_{\mRat_{t}\downarrow 0} \Ex_t [{\mRat}_{t+1}/\mRat_t] > 1 > \lim_{\mRat_{t}\uparrow \infty} \Ex_t [{\mRat}_{t+1}/\mRat_t]$
\item The intermediate value theorem
\end{enumerate}
% which can be differentiated and rearranged to yield\hypertarget{mTargDerImplicit}{}
\begin{align}
\bar{\Rnorm}(1-\usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mTrg)) & = 1 \\
(1-\usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mTrg)) & = \bar{\Rnorm}^{-1} \\
% 1-\bar{\Rnorm}^{-1} & = \usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mTrg). \label{eq:mTargDerImplicit}
\end{align}
The fact (cf.\~\eqref{eq:MinMPCDef}) that the minimum value of $\usual{\cFunc}^{\prime}$ is $1-\PatR$ converts~\eqref{eq:mTargDerImplicit} to the inequality $1-\bar{\Rnorm}^{-1} > 1-\PatR$ from which we have
\begin{align}
\PGroAdj/\Rfree & > \Pat/\Rfree \notag
\\ 1 & > \Pat/\PGroAdj
\end{align}
which is the {\GICNrm}; thus, if a stable point exists, it must satisfy the {\GICNrm}. (The appendix proves that if the {\GICNrm} is satisfied, such a point must exist, and be globally stable).
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{Collective-Stability}{}
\hypertarget{pseudo-steady-state}{}
\subsubsection{The Unexpectedly Expected Individual Balanced Growth `pseudo steady state'}\label{subsubsec:mSteadyState}
A traditional question in macroeconomic models is whether there is a `balanced growth' equilibrium in which aggregate variables (income, consumption, market resources) all grow forever at the same rate. For our model, Figure~\ref{fig:cGroTargetFig} showed that there is no single $\mRat$ for which $\Ex_{t}[\mRatBF_{t+1}]/\mRatBF_{t} = \Ex_{t}[\cLevBF_{t+1}]/\cLevBF_{t} = \PGro$~for an individual consumer. Nevertheless, the next section will show that economies populated by collections of such consumers can exhibit balanced growth in the aggregate, and in the cross-section of households.